Difference between revisions of "Natural Numbers:Well-Ordering"

From Department of Mathematics at UTSA
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with "In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of positive integers is w...")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which {\displaystyle x}x precedes {\displaystyle y}y if and only if {\displaystyle y}y is either {\displaystyle x}x or the sum of {\displaystyle x}x and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering {\displaystyle 2,4,6,...}{\displaystyle 2,4,6,...}; and {\displaystyle 1,3,5,...}{\displaystyle 1,3,5,...}).
+
In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element. In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which <math>x</math> precedes <math>y</math> if and only if <math>y</math> is either <math>x</math> or the sum of <math>x</math> and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering <math>2,4,6,...</math>; and <math>1,3,5,...</math>).
  
The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers {\displaystyle \{\ldots ,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,\ldots \}}{\displaystyle \{\ldots ,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,\ldots \}} contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.
+
The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers <math>\{... ,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...\}</math> contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.
  
 
Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:
 
Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:
  
 
In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
 
In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set {\displaystyle A}A of natural numbers has an infimum, say {\displaystyle a^{*}}a^{*}. We can now find an integer {\displaystyle n^{*}}n^{*} such that {\displaystyle a^{*}}a^{*} lies in the half-open interval {\displaystyle (n^{*}-1,n^{*}]}{\displaystyle (n^{*}-1,n^{*}]}, and can then show that we must have {\displaystyle a^{*}=n^{*}}{\displaystyle a^{*}=n^{*}}, and {\displaystyle n^{*}}n^{*} in {\displaystyle A}A.
+
Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set <math>A</math> of natural numbers has an infimum, say <math>a^{*}}a^{*}</math>. We can now find an integer <math>n^{*}}n^{*}</math> such that <math>a^{*}}a^{*}</math> lies in the half-open interval <math>(n^{*}-1,n^{*}]</math>, and can then show that we must have <math>a^{*}=n^{*}</math>, and <math>n^{*}}n^{*}</math> in <math>A</math>.
In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers {\displaystyle n}n such that "{\displaystyle \{0,\ldots ,n\}}{\displaystyle \{0,\ldots ,n\}} is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.
+
In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers <math>n</math> such that "<math>\{0,\ldots ,n\}</math> is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.
In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set {\displaystyle S}S, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".
+
In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set <math>S</math>, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".
 +
 
 +
==Resources==
 +
* [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Well-ordering_principle Well-ordering principle], Wikipedia

Revision as of 13:09, 12 October 2021

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element. In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which precedes if and only if is either or the sum of and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering ; and ).

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic. Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set of natural numbers has an infimum, say Failed to parse (MathML with SVG or PNG fallback (recommended for modern browsers and accessibility tools): Invalid response ("Math extension cannot connect to Restbase.") from server "https://wikimedia.org/api/rest_v1/":): {\displaystyle a^{*}}a^{*}} . We can now find an integer Failed to parse (syntax error): {\displaystyle n^{*}}n^{*}} such that Failed to parse (syntax error): {\displaystyle a^{*}}a^{*}} lies in the half-open interval , and can then show that we must have , and Failed to parse (syntax error): {\displaystyle n^{*}}n^{*}} in . In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers such that " is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered. In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set , assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Resources