Real Numbers

From Department of Mathematics at UTSA
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Why we need the real numbers

This is a good juncture to justify the subject of real analysis, which essentially reduces to justifying the necessity of studying . So, what is missing? Why do we need anything beyond the rationals?

The first sign of trouble is square roots. Famously, is not rational – in other words, there is no rational number which squares to (see the exercises). This fact has a curious consequence – consider the following function:

Clearly this function has a dramatic jump in it around the rational , where it suddenly changes from being equal to zero and starts being equal to one. However, it's difficult (or even impossible) to pin down exactly where this jump happens. Any specific rational number is safely on one side or the other, and, indeed, in the standard Topology on , this function is continuous (don't worry if that makes no sense to you).

It is this flaw which the real numbers are designed to repair. We will define the real numbers so that no matter how clever we try to be, if a function has a 'jump' in the way that does, then we will always be able to find a specific number at which it jumps.

The following sections describe the properties of which make this possible.

Different perspectives

In order to prove anything about the real numbers, we need to know what their properties are. There are two different approaches to describing these properties – axiomatic and constructive.

An axiomatic approach

When we take an axiomatic approach, we simply make a series of assertions regarding , and assume that they hold.

The assertions that we make are called axioms – in a mathematical context this term means roughly 'basic assumption'.

The advantage of this approach is that it is then clear exactly what has been assumed, before proceeding to deduce results which rely only on those assumptions.

The disadvantage of this approach is that it might not be immediately clear that any object satisfying the properties we desire even exists!

A constructive approach

With a constructive approach, we are not happy simply to assume exactly what we want, but rather we try to construct from something simpler, and then prove that it has the properties we want. In this way, what could have been axioms become theorems. There are several different ways to do this, starting from and using some method to 'fill up the gaps between the rationals'.

All of these methods are fairly complex and will be put off until the next section.

The axioms

So, what are these axioms which we will need? The short version is to say that is a complete ordered field. This is in fact saying a great many things:

  • That is a totally ordered field.
  • That is complete in this ordering (Note that the meaning of completeness here is not quite the same as the common meaning in the study of partially ordered sets).
  • That the algebraic operations (addition and multiplication) described by the field axioms interact with the ordering in the expected manner.

In more detail, we assert the following:

  1. is a field. For this, we require binary operations addition (denoted ) and multiplication (denoted ) defined on , and distinct elements and satisfying:
    1. is a commutative group, meaning:
      1. (associativity)
      2. (commutativity)
      3. (identity)
      4. (inverse)
    2. is a commutative group, meaning:
      1. (associativity)
      2. (commutativity)
      3. (identity)
      4. (inverse)
    3. (distributivity)
  2. is a totally ordered set. For this we require a relation (denoted by ) satisfying:
    1. (reflexivity)
    2. (transitivity)
    3. (anti-symmetry)
    4. (totality)
  3. is complete in this order (see below for details).
  4. The field operations and order interact in the expected manner, meaning:

This is a substantial list, and if you are not used to axiomatic mathematics (or even if you are!) it may seem somewhat daunting, especially since we have yet to give details of what completeness means. This is amongst the longest list of axioms in any region of mathematics, but if you examine each in turn, you will find that they all state things which you have probably taken for granted as 'the way numbers behave' without a second thought.

These axioms are so exacting that there is a sense in which they specify the real numbers precisely. In other words is the only complete ordered field.

The complete ordered field

The real numbers are often described as "the complete ordered field", a phrase that can be interpreted in several ways.

First, an order can be lattice-complete. It is easy to see that no ordered field can be lattice-complete, because it can have no largest element (given any element z, z + 1 is larger).

Additionally, an order can be Dedekind-complete. The uniqueness result at the end of that section justifies using the word "the" in the phrase "complete ordered field" when this is the sense of "complete" that is meant. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Dedekind cuts, since that construction starts from an ordered field (the rationals) and then forms the Dedekind-completion of it in a standard way.

These two notions of completeness ignore the field structure. However, an ordered group (in this case, the additive group of the field) defines a uniform structure, and uniform structures have a notion of completeness; the description in § Completeness is a special case. (We refer to the notion of completeness in uniform spaces rather than the related and better known notion for metric spaces, since the definition of metric space relies on already having a characterization of the real numbers.) It is not true that is the only uniformly complete ordered field, but it is the only uniformly complete Archimedean field, and indeed one often hears the phrase "complete Archimedean field" instead of "complete ordered field". Every uniformly complete Archimedean field must also be Dedekind-complete (and vice versa), justifying using "the" in the phrase "the complete Archimedean field". This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Cauchy sequences (the construction carried out in full in this article), since it starts with an Archimedean field (the rationals) and forms the uniform completion of it in a standard way.

But the original use of the phrase "complete Archimedean field" was by David Hilbert, who meant still something else by it. He meant that the real numbers form the largest Archimedean field in the sense that every other Archimedean field is a subfield of . Thus is "complete" in the sense that nothing further can be added to it without making it no longer an Archimedean field. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from surreal numbers, since that construction starts with a proper class that contains every ordered field (the surreals) and then selects from it the largest Archimedean subfield.

Further notation

Having defined these operations and relations on , we need to introduce more notation to aid in talking about them. Hopefully all these conventions should be familiar to you, but it is important to formally present them all to avoid confusion following from misunderstanding of notation:

  • Rather than writing for multiplication, we may simply denote it by juxtaposition. In other words, we write to denote .
  • Since both multiplication and addition are associative, we omit unnecessary bracketing when several numbers are added or multiplied. In other words, rather than writing or , which are equal, we simply write to denote their common value.
  • To further save writing of brackets, by convention, multiplication has a higher precedence than addition. So, for example, the expression should be interpreted as , not as .
  • The number is called the sum of and .
  • The number is called the product of and .
  • The additive inverse of is written , and called the negative or negation of . So, .
  • The multiplicative inverse of is written , and called the reciprocal, or simply the inverse of . So, .
  • We define the binary operation of subtraction as follows: For , we set . The number is called the difference of and .
  • Subtraction has the same precedence as addition (less than that of multiplication), and when the two operations are mixed without bracketing, left-associativity is implied. For example, should be interpreted as .
  • We define the binary operation of division as follows: For , with , we set . The number is called the quotient of and , and is also denoted .
  • Division has a higher precedence than that of addition or subtraction, but there is no simple convention as to how to handle mixed multiplication and division. Using the notation, rather than the notation helps to avoid confusion.
  • We define the binary operation of exponentation as follows: For and we define recursively by and . Then for , with , we define .
  • Exponentation has a higher precedence than any of division, multiplication, addition and subtraction. For example, should be interpreted as .
  • We write to mean .
  • We write to mean and .
  • We write to mean .
  • To abbreviate a collection of equalities or inequalities, they may be strung together. For example, the expression should be interpreted as and and and .
  • To say is positive means .
  • To say is negative means .
  • To say is non-positive means .
  • To say is non-negative means .
  • We also introduce notation for several common varieties of subsets of . All of these subsets are called intervals:
    • (called the closed interval from to )
    • (called the open interval from to )
    • In all these cases, is called the lower limit of the interval, and is called the upper limit.
    • An excluded lower limit (as in the second and fourth cases) may be replaced by to indicate that there is no lower restriction. For example .
    • Similarly, an excluded upper limit (as in the second and third cases) may be replaced by . For example, .
    • Some specific intervals which appear frequently are the closed unit interval, or just unit interval, which is , and , the positive real numbers.

Completeness

The rational numbers satisfy all of the axioms above which have been explained in detail, and so if we are to escape the problem which we described above then we clearly need something more. This 'something more' is completeness. There are several equivalent ways of describing completeness, but most of them require us to know about sequences, which we do not introduce until the next chapter, so for the moment we can only give one definition.

Upper bounds

Let . We say is an upper bound for if

For example, is an upper bound for , as is , but is not, because and . A set with an upper bound is said to be bounded above by .

Least Upper Bound

We say is a least upper bound or supremum for if is an upper bound for , and is any upper bound for then . More formally:

Similarly, we say is a lower bound for if

and we say is a greatest lower bound or infimum for if:

The supremum and infimum of a set are denoted and respectively.

The Least upper bound axiom

Now we are finally ready to state the last axiom:

  • If is non-empty and has an upper bound, then has a least upper bound in .

This is the axiom of the real numbers that finally satisfies what was lacking in the rationals: completeness. It is worth noting at this point, to avoid possible confusion, that in the study of general partially ordered sets, the definition of completeness is that every subset has a least upper bound, and there is no condition that they be non-empty or bounded above. Nevertheless, we really do wish to impose these two conditions in this case.

Other completeness axioms

There are other equivalent ways to state the completeness axiom, but they involve sequences, so we shall delay them until after the discussion of that topic. Because of the existence of these other forms, this axiom is sometimes called the least upper bound axiom.

The complete ordered field

The real numbers are often described as "the complete ordered field", a phrase that can be interpreted in several ways.

First, an order can be lattice-complete. It is easy to see that no ordered field can be lattice-complete, because it can have no largest element (given any element z, Template:Nowrap is larger).

Additionally, an order can be Dedekind-complete. The uniqueness result at the end of that section justifies using the word "the" in the phrase "complete ordered field" when this is the sense of "complete" that is meant. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Dedekind cuts, since that construction starts from an ordered field (the rationals) and then forms the Dedekind-completion of it in a standard way.

These two notions of completeness ignore the field structure. However, an ordered group (in this case, the additive group of the field) defines a uniform structure, and uniform structures have a notion of completeness; the description in § Completeness is a special case. (We refer to the notion of completeness in uniform spaces rather than the related and better known notion for metric spaces, since the definition of metric space relies on already having a characterization of the real numbers.) It is not true that is the only uniformly complete ordered field, but it is the only uniformly complete Archimedean field, and indeed one often hears the phrase "complete Archimedean field" instead of "complete ordered field". Every uniformly complete Archimedean field must also be Dedekind-complete (and vice versa), justifying using "the" in the phrase "the complete Archimedean field". This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Cauchy sequences (the construction carried out in full in this article), since it starts with an Archimedean field (the rationals) and forms the uniform completion of it in a standard way.

But the original use of the phrase "complete Archimedean field" was by David Hilbert, who meant still something else by it. He meant that the real numbers form the largest Archimedean field in the sense that every other Archimedean field is a subfield of . Thus is "complete" in the sense that nothing further can be added to it without making it no longer an Archimedean field. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from surreal numbers, since that construction starts with a proper class that contains every ordered field (the surreals) and then selects from it the largest Archimedean subfield.

Licensing

Content obtained and/or adapted from: